Mathematical Logic
نویسندگان
چکیده
We show that a strong form of the so called Lindström’s Theorem [4] fails to generalize to extensions of Lκω and Lκκ : For weakly compact κ there is no strongest extension of Lκω with the (κ, κ)-compactness property and the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem down to κ . With an additional set-theoretic assumption, there is no strongest extension of Lκκ with the (κ, κ)-compactness property and the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem down to < κ . By a well-known theorem of Lindström [4], first order logicLωω is the strongest logic which satisifies the compactness theorem and the downward LöwenheimSkolem theorem. For weakly compact κ , the infinitary logic Lκω satisfies both the (κ, κ)-compactness property and the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem down to κ . In [1] Jon Barwise pointed out that Lκω is not maximal with respect to these properties, and asked what is the strongest logic based on a weakly compact cardinal κ which still satisfies the (κ, κ)-compactness property and some other natural conditions suggested by κ . We prove (Corollary 5) that for weakly compact κ there is no strongest extension of Lκω with the (κ, κ)-compactness property and the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem down to κ . This shows that there is no extension of Lκω which would satisify the most obvious generalization of Lindström’s Theorem. A stronger result (Theorem 11) is proved under an additional assumption. We use the notation and terminology of [2, Chapter II] as much as possible. We will work with concrete logics such as first order logic Lωω, infinitary logic Lκλ and their extensions Lωω({Qi : i ∈ I }) and Lκλ({Qi : i ∈ I }) by generalized quantifiers. Therefore it is not at all critical which definition of a logic one uses as long as these logics are included and some basic closure properties are respected. We use L ≤ L′ to denote the sublogic relation. Let P be a property of logics. A logic L∗ is strongest extension of L with P , if ∗ We are indebted to Lauri Hella, Tapani Hyttinen and Kerkko Luosto for useful suggestions. S. Shelah: Institute of Mathematics, Hebrew University, Jerusalem, Israel. Research partially supported by the United States-Israel Binational Science Foundation. Publication number [ShVa:726] J. Väänänen: Department of Mathematics, University of Helsinki, Helsinki, Finland. e-mail: [email protected] Research partially supported by grant 40734 of the Academy of Finland. 64 S. Shelah, J. Väänänen 1. L ≤ L∗, 2. L∗ has property P , and whenever L is a sublogic L′ and L′ has property P , then L′ ≤ L∗. Let L be a logic and κ and λ infinite cardinals. L is (κ, λ)-compact if for all ⊆ L of power κ , if each subset of of cardinality < λ has a model, then has a model. L is κ-compact if it is (κ, ω)-compact. L is weakly κ-compact if L is (κ, κ)-compact. L is fully compact if it is κ-compact for all κ . L has the Löwenheim-Skolem property down to κ , denoted by LS(κ) if every φ ∈ L which has a model, has a model of cardinality ≤ κ . If every sentence φ ∈ L which has a model, has a model of cardinality < κ , we say that L satisfies LS(< κ). The order-type of the well-ordering R is denoted by otp(R). Theorem 1. [4] The logic Lωω is strongest extension of Lωω with א0-compactness and LS(א0). Let C be a class of cardinals. Let A |= Q Cxyφ(x, y, z) ⇐⇒ {〈a, b〉 : A |= φ(a, b, c)} is a linear order with cofinality in C. By [9], Lωω(Q C) is always fully compact. For C an interval we use the notation Q [κ,λ) and Q cf [κ,λ]. Proposition 2. There is no strongest κ-compact extension of Lωω. In fact: 1. there are fully compact logics Ln, n < ω, such that Ln ≤ Ln+1 for all n < ω, but no א0-compact logic extends each Ln. 2. There is an א0-compact logic L1 and a fully compact logic L2 such that no א0-compact logic extends both L1 and L2. Proof. LetLn = Lωω({Q [אω,∞]}∪{Q אl : l < n}). By [9], eachLn is fully compact. Clearly, no א0-compact logic can extend each Ln. For the second claim, let L1 be the logic Lωω(Q1), where Q1 is the quantifier “there exists uncountable many” introduced by Mostowski [8]. This logic is א0-compact [3], see [2, Chapter IV] for more recent results. Let L2 be the logic Lωω(QB), where QB is the quantifier “there is a branch” introduced by Shelah [10]. More exactly, QBxytuM(x)T (y)(t ≤ u) if and only if ≤T is a partial order of T ⊆ M and there are D,≤D , f and B such that: 1. ≤D is a total order of D ⊆ M 2. f : 〈T ,≤T 〉 → 〈D,≤D〉 is strictly increasing 3. ∀s ∈ D∃p ∈ T (f (p) = s) 4. B ⊆ T is totally ordered by ≤T 5. ∀b ∈ B((p ∈ T &p ≤T b) → p ∈ B) 6. ∀s ∈ D∃b ∈ B(s ≤D f (b)). The reader is referred to [10] for a proof of the full compactness of L2. A note on extensions of infinitary logic 65 Suppose there were an א0-compact logic L containing both L1 and L2 as a sublogic. It is easy to see that the class of countable well-orders can be expressed as a relativized pseudoelementary class in L. This contradicts א0-compactness of L. Lauri Hella pointed out that by elaborating the proof of claim (2) of the above proposition, we can make L1 fully compact. It was proved in [11] that, assuming GCH, there is no strongest extension of Lωω which is א0-compact. Our proof of (1) of the above proposition essentially occurs in a note, based on a suggestion of Paolo Lipparini, added after Theorem 8 of [11]. Proposition 3. Suppose κ > א0. There is no strongest extension of Lκ+ω with LS(κ). Proof. Let L1 = Lκ+ω(Qcf א0) and L2 = Lκ+ω(Qcf [א1,κ]). By using standard arguments with elementary chains of submodels, it is easy to see that both L1 and L2 have LS(κ), but the consistent sentence R is a linear order with no last element ∧ ¬Qcf א0xyR(x, y) ∧ ¬Qcf [א1,κ]xyR(x, y) has no models of size ≤ κ . It was proved in [11] that there is no strongest extension of Lωω with LS(ω). Lemma 4. Suppose κ is weakly compact. Then Lκω(Q cf {א0}) and Lκω(Q cf [א1,κ]) are weakly κ-compact. Moreover, if κ > ω, these logics satisfy LS(κ). Proof. The claim concerning LS(κ) is proved with a standard elementary chain argument. We prove the weak compactness ofLκω(Q [א1,κ]). The case ofLκω(Q {א0}) is similar, but easier. For this end, suppose T is a set of sentences of Lκω(Q [א1,κ]) and |T | = κ . We may assume T ⊆ κ . If α < κ , then we assume that there is a model Mα |= T ∩ α. In view of LS(κ), it is not a loss of generality to assume that Mα = 〈κ,Rα〉, where Rα ⊆ κ × κ . Let R(α, β, γ ) ⇐⇒ Rα(β, γ ). By weak compactness there is a transitive M of cardinality κ such that 〈H(κ), , T , R〉 ≺Lκκ 〈M, , T ∗, R∗〉 and κ ∈ M . Let M = 〈M,S〉, where S(x, y) ⇐⇒ R∗(κ, x, y). We claim that M |= T . We need only worry about the cofinality-quantifier. Cofinalities < κ can be expressed in Lκκ , so they are preserved both ways. Therefore also cofinality κ is preserved, and no other cofinalities can occur as the models have cardinality κ . Since the logics Lκω(Q א0)) and Lκω(Q [א1,κ]) cannot both be sublogics of a logic with LS(κ), we get from the above lemma: Corollary 5. Suppose κ > ω is weakly compact. Then there is no strongest weakly κ-compact extension of Lκω with LS(κ). 66 S. Shelah, J. Väänänen The logic Lκω actually satisfies the property LS(< κ) which is stronger than LS(κ). To prove a result like the above corollary for the property LS(< κ) we have to work a little harder. At the same time we extend the proof to extensions of Lκκ . Here the cofinality quantifiers Q C will not help as Q cf {λ} is definable in Lκκ for λ < κ . Therefore we use more refined order-type quantifiers. Definition 6. Let Lκλ(Q) denote the formal extension of Lκλ by the generalized quantifier symbol Qxyφ(x, y, z). If Y is a class of ordinals, we get a logic Lκλ(Q,Y) from Lκλ(Q) by defining the semantics by A |= Qxyφ(x, y, c) ⇐⇒ otp({〈a, b〉 : A |= φ(a, b, c)}) ∈ Y . If φ ∈ Lκλ(Q,Y) and A |= φ, we say that A |= φ holds in the Y-interpretation. If A is a model, then
منابع مشابه
Linear Formulas in Continuous Logic
We prove that continuous sentences preserved by the ultramean construction (a generalization of the ultraproduct construction) are exactly those sentences which are approximated by linear sentences. Continuous sentences preserved by linear elementary equivalence are exactly those sentences which are approximated in the Riesz space generated by linear sentences. Also, characterizations for linea...
متن کاملDesigning a Meta-Heuristic Algorithm Based on a Simple Seeking Logic
Nowadays, in majority of academic contexts, it has been tried to consider the highest possible level of similarities to the real world. Hence, most of the problems have complicated structures. Traditional methods for solving almost all of the mathematical and optimization problems are inefficient. As a result, meta-heuristic algorithms have been employed increasingly during recent years. In thi...
متن کاملBeyond First Order Logic: From number of structures to structure of numbers: Part I
We study the history and recent developments in nonelementarymodel theory focusing on the framework of abstractelementary classes. We discuss the role of syntax and semanticsand the motivation to generalize first order model theory to nonelementaryframeworks and illuminate the study with concrete examplesof classes of models. This first part introduces the main conceps and philosophies anddiscu...
متن کاملBeyond first order logic: From number of structures to structure of numbers: Part II
We study the history and recent developments in nonelementarymodel theory focusing on the framework of abstractelementary classes. We discuss the role of syntax and semanticsand the motivation to generalize first order model theory to nonelementaryframeworks and illuminate the study with concrete examplesof classes of models. This second part continues to study the question of catecoricitytrans...
متن کاملDistributed Contingency Logic and Security
In information security, ignorance is not bliss. It is always stated that hiding the protocols (let the other be ignorant about it) does not increase the security of organizations. However, there are cases that ignorance creates protocols. In this paper, we propose distributed contingency logic, a proper extension of contingency (ignorance) logic. Intuitively, a formula is distributed contingen...
متن کاملOn the multivariate process capability vector in fuzzy environment
The production of a process is expected to meet customer demands, specifications or engineering tolerances. The ability of a process to meet these expectations is expresed as a single number using a process capability index. When the quality of the products relates to more than one characteristic, multivariate process capability indices are applied. As it is known, in some circumstances we are ...
متن کاملذخیره در منابع من
با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید
عنوان ژورنال:
دوره شماره
صفحات -
تاریخ انتشار 2000